(2023) Students for Fair Admissions v. Harvard and Students for Fair Admissions v. University of North Carolina

US Supreme Court

US Supreme Court

Photo by Joe Ravi (CC-BY-SA 3.0)

STUDENTS FOR FAIR ADMISSIONS, INC. v. President and Fellows of Harvard College

certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the first circuit

________________________________________

No. 20โ€“1199. Argued October 31, 2022โ€”Decided June 29, 2023

________________________________________

Harvard College and the University of North Carolina (UNC) are two of the oldest institutions of higher learning in the United States. Every year, tens of thousands of students apply to each school; many fewer are admitted. Both Harvard and UNC employ a highly selective admissions process to make their decisions. Admission to each school can depend on a studentโ€™s grades, recommendation letters, or extracurricular involvement. It can also depend on their race. The question presented is whether the admissions systems used by Harvard College and UNC are lawful under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

At Harvard, each application for admission is initially screened by a โ€œfirst reader,โ€ who assigns a numerical score in each of six categories: academic, extracurricular, athletic, school support, personal, and overall. For the โ€œoverallโ€ categoryโ€”a composite of the five other ratingsโ€”a first reader can and does consider the applicantโ€™s race. Harvardโ€™s admissions subcommittees then review all applications from a particular geographic area. These regional subcommittees make recommendations to the full admissions committee, and they take an applicantโ€™s race into account. When the 40-member full admissions committee begins its deliberations, it discusses the relative breakdown of applicants by race. The goal of the process, according to Harvardโ€™s director of admissions, is ensuring there is no โ€œdramatic drop-offโ€ in minority admissions from the prior class. An applicant receiving a majority of the full committeeโ€™s votes is tentatively accepted for admission. At the end of this process, the racial composition of the tentative applicant pool is disclosed to the committee. The last stage of Harvardโ€™s admissions process, called the โ€œlop,โ€ winnows the list of tentatively admitted students to arrive at the final class. Applicants that Harvard considers cutting at this stage are placed on the โ€œlop list,โ€ which contains only four pieces of information: legacy status, recruited athlete status, financial aid eligibility, and race. In the Harvard admissions process, โ€œrace is a determinative tip forโ€ a significant percentage โ€œof all admitted African American and Hispanic applicants.โ€

UNC has a similar admissions process. Every application is reviewed first by an admissions office reader, who assigns a numerical rating to each of several categories. Readers are required to consider the applicantโ€™s race as a factor in their review. Readers then make a written recommendation on each assigned application, and they may provide an applicant a substantial โ€œplusโ€ depending on the applicantโ€™s race. At this stage, most recommendations are provisionally final. A committee of experienced staff members then conducts a โ€œschool group reviewโ€ of every initial decision made by a reader and either approves or rejects the recommendation. In making those decisions, the committee may consider the applicantโ€™s race.

Petitioner, Students for Fair Admissions (SFFA), is a nonprofit organization whose stated purpose is โ€œto defend human and civil rights secured by law, including the right of individuals to equal protection under the law.โ€ SFFA filed separate lawsuits against Harvard and UNC, arguing that their race-based admissions programs violate, respectively, Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 and the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. After separate bench trials, both admissions programs were found permissible under the Equal Protection Clause and this Courtโ€™s precedents. In the Harvard case, the First Circuit affirmed, and this Court granted certiorari. In the UNC case, this Court granted certiorari before judgment.

Held: Harvardโ€™s and UNCโ€™s admissions programs violate the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Pp. 6โ€“40.

(a) Because SFFA complies with the standing requirements for organizational plaintiffs articulated by this Court in Hunt v. Washington State Apple Advertising Commโ€™n, 432 U. S. 333, SFFAโ€™s obligations under Article III are satisfied, and this Court has jurisdiction to consider the merits of SFFAโ€™s claims.

The Court rejects UNCโ€™s argument that SFFA lacks standing because it is not a โ€œgenuineโ€ membership organization. An organizational plaintiff can satisfy Article III jurisdiction in two ways, one of which is to assert โ€œstanding solely as the representative of its members,โ€ Warth v. Seldin, 422 U. S. 490, 511, an approach known as representational or organizational standing. To invoke it, an organization must satisfy the three-part test in Hunt. Respondents do not suggest that SFFA fails Huntโ€™s test for organizational standing. They argue instead that SFFA cannot invoke organizational standing at all because SFFA was not a genuine membership organization at the time it filed suit. Respondents maintain that, under Hunt, a group qualifies as a genuine membership organization only if it is controlled and funded by its members. In Hunt, this Court determined that a state agency with no traditional members could still qualify as a genuine membership organization in substance because the agency represented the interests of individuals and otherwise satisfied Huntโ€™s three-part test for organizational standing. See 432 U. S., at 342. Huntโ€™s โ€œindicia of membershipโ€ analysis, however, has no applicability here. As the courts below found, SFFA is indisputably a voluntary membership organization with identifiable members who support its mission and whom SFFA represents in good faith. SFFA is thus entitled to rely on the organizational standing doctrine as articulated in Hunt. Pp. 6โ€“9.

(b) Proposed by Congress and ratified by the States in the wake of the Civil War, the Fourteenth Amendment provides that no State shall โ€œdeny to any person . . . the equal protection of the laws.โ€ Proponents of the Equal Protection Clause described its โ€œfoundation[al] principleโ€ as โ€œnot permit[ing] any distinctions of law based on race or color.โ€ Any โ€œlaw which operates upon one man,โ€ they maintained, should โ€œoperate equally upon all.โ€ Accordingly, as this Courtโ€™s early decisions interpreting the Equal Protection Clause explained, the Fourteenth Amendment guaranteed โ€œthat the law in the States shall be the same for the black as for the white; that all persons, whether colored or white, shall stand equal before the laws of the States.โ€

Despite the early recognition of the broad sweep of the Equal Protection Clause, the Courtโ€”alongside the countryโ€”quickly failed to live up to the Clauseโ€™s core commitments. For almost a century after the Civil War, state-mandated segregation was in many parts of the Nation a regrettable norm. This Court played its own role in that ignoble history, allowing in Plessy v. Ferguson the separate but equal regime that would come to deface much of America. 163 U. S. 537.

After Plessy, โ€œAmerican courts . . . labored with the doctrine [of separate but equal] for over half a century.โ€ Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483, 491. Some cases in this period attempted to curtail the perniciousness of the doctrine by emphasizing that it required States to provide black students educational opportunities equal toโ€”even if formally separate fromโ€”those enjoyed by white students. See, e.g., Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U. S. 337, 349โ€“350. But the inherent folly of that approachโ€”of trying to derive equality from inequalityโ€”soon became apparent. As the Court subsequently recognized, even racial distinctions that were argued to have no palpable effect worked to subordinate the afflicted students. See, e.g., McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents for Higher Ed., 339 U. S. 637, 640โ€“642. By 1950, the inevitable truth of the Fourteenth Amendment had thus begun to reemerge: Separate cannot be equal.

The culmination of this approach came finally in Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483. There, the Court overturned the separate but equal regime established in Plessy and began on the path of invalidating all de jure racial discrimination by the States and Federal Government. The conclusion reached by the Brown Court was unmistakably clear: the right to a public education โ€œmust be made available to all on equal terms.โ€ 347 U. S., at 493. The Court reiterated that rule just one year later, holding that โ€œfull complianceโ€ with Brown required schools to admit students โ€œon a racially nondiscriminatory basis.โ€ Brown v. Board of Education, 349 U. S. 294, 300โ€“301.

In the years that followed, Brownโ€™s โ€œfundamental principle that racial discrimination in public education is unconstitutional,โ€ id., at 298, reached other areas of lifeโ€”for example, state and local laws requiring segregation in busing, Gayle v. Browder, 352 U. S. 903 (per curiam); racial segregation in the enjoyment of public beaches and bathhouses Mayor and City Council of Baltimore v. Dawson, 350 U. S. 877 (per curiam); and antimiscegenation laws, Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S. 1. These decisions, and others like them, reflect the โ€œcore purposeโ€ of the Equal Protection Clause: โ€œdo[ing] away with all governmentally imposed discrimination based on race.โ€ Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U. S. 429, 432.

Eliminating racial discrimination means eliminating all of it. Accordingly, the Court has held that the Equal Protection Clause applies โ€œwithout regard to any differences of race, of color, or of nationalityโ€โ€”it is โ€œuniversal in [its] application.โ€ Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356, 369. For โ€œ[t]he guarantee of equal protection cannot mean one thing when applied to one individual and something else when applied to a person of another color.โ€ Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U. S. 265, 289โ€“290.

Any exceptions to the Equal Protection Clauseโ€™s guarantee must survive a daunting two-step examination known as โ€œstrict scrutiny,โ€ Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peรฑa, 515 U. S. 200, 227, which asks first whether the racial classification is used to โ€œfurther compelling governmental interests,โ€ Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306, 326, and second whether the governmentโ€™s use of race is โ€œnarrowly tailored,โ€ i.e., โ€œnecessary,โ€ to achieve that interest, Fisher v. University of Tex. at Austin, 570 U. S. 297, 311โ€“312. Acceptance of race-based state action is rare for a reason: โ€œ[d]istinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry are by their very nature odious to a free people whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality.โ€ Rice v. Cayetano, 528 U. S. 495, 517. Pp. 9โ€“16.

(c) This Court first considered whether a university may make race-based admissions decisions in Bakke, 438 U. S. 265. In a deeply splintered decision that produced six different opinions, Justice Powellโ€™s opinion for himself alone would eventually come to โ€œserv[e] as the touchstone for constitutional analysis of race-conscious admissions policies.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 323. After rejecting three of the Universityโ€™s four justifications as not sufficiently compelling, Justice Powell turned to its last interest asserted to be compellingโ€”obtaining the educational benefits that flow from a racially diverse student body. Justice Powell found that interest to be โ€œa constitutionally permissible goal for an institution of higher education,โ€ which was entitled as a matter of academic freedom โ€œto make its own judgments as to . . . the selection of its student body.โ€ 438 U. S., at 311โ€“312. But a universityโ€™s freedom was not unlimitedโ€”โ€œ[r]acial and ethnic distinctions of any sort are inherently suspect,โ€ Justice Powell explained, and antipathy toward them was deeply โ€œrooted in our Nationโ€™s constitutional and demographic history.โ€ Id., at 291. Accordingly, a university could not employ a two-track quota system with a specific number of seats reserved for individuals from a preferred ethnic group. Id., at 315. Neither still could a university use race to foreclose an individual from all consideration. Id., at 318. Race could only operate as โ€œa โ€˜plusโ€™ in a particular applicantโ€™s file,โ€ and even then it had to be weighed in a manner โ€œflexible enough to consider all pertinent elements of diversity in light of the particular qualifications of each applicant.โ€ Id., at 317. Pp. 16โ€“19.

(d) For years following Bakke, lower courts struggled to determine whether Justice Powellโ€™s decision was โ€œbinding precedent.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 325. Then, in Grutter v. Bollinger, the Court for the first time โ€œendorse[d] Justice Powellโ€™s view that student body diversity is a compelling state interest that can justify the use of race in university admissions.โ€ Ibid. The Grutter majorityโ€™s analysis tracked Justice Powellโ€™s in many respects, including its insistence on limits on how universities may consider race in their admissions programs. Those limits, Grutter explained, were intended to guard against two dangers that all race-based government action portends. The first is the risk that the use of race will devolve into โ€œillegitimate . . . stereotyp[ing].โ€ Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 488 U. S. 469, 493 (plurality opinion). Admissions programs could thus not operate on the โ€œbelief that minority students always (or even consistently) express some characteristic minority viewpoint on any issue.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 333 (internal quotation marks omitted). The second risk is that race would be used not as a plus, but as a negativeโ€”to discriminate against those racial groups that were not the beneficiaries of the race-based preference. A universityโ€™s use of race, accordingly, could not occur in a manner that โ€œunduly harm[ed] nonminority applicants.โ€ Id., at 341.

To manage these concerns, Grutter imposed one final limit on race-based admissions programs: At some point, the Court held, they must end. Id., at 342. Recognizing that โ€œ[e]nshrining a permanent justification for racial preferences would offendโ€ the Constitutionโ€™s unambiguous guarantee of equal protection, the Court expressed its expectation that, in 25 years, โ€œthe use of racial preferences will no longer be necessary to further the interest approved today.โ€ Id., at 343. Pp. 19โ€“21.

(e) Twenty years have passed since Grutter, with no end to race-based college admissions in sight. But the Court has permitted race-based college admissions only within the confines of narrow restrictions: such admissions programs must comply with strict scrutiny, may never use race as a stereotype or negative, and mustโ€”at some pointโ€”end. Respondentsโ€™ admissions systems fail each of these criteria and must therefore be invalidated under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. Pp. 21โ€“34.

(1) Respondents fail to operate their race-based admissions programs in a manner that is โ€œsufficiently measurable to permit judicial [review]โ€ under the rubric of strict scrutiny. Fisher v. University of Tex. at Austin, 579 U. S. 365, 381. First, the interests that respondents view as compelling cannot be subjected to meaningful judicial review. Those interests include training future leaders, acquiring new knowledge based on diverse outlooks, promoting a robust marketplace of ideas, and preparing engaged and productive citizens. While these are commendable goals, they are not sufficiently coherent for purposes of strict scrutiny. It is unclear how courts are supposed to measure any of these goals, or if they could, to know when they have been reached so that racial preferences can end. The elusiveness of respondentsโ€™ asserted goals is further illustrated by comparing them to recognized compelling interests. For example, courts can discern whether the temporary racial segregation of inmates will prevent harm to those in the prison, see Johnson v. California, 543 U. S. 499, 512โ€“513, but the question whether a particular mix of minority students produces โ€œengaged and productive citizensโ€ or effectively โ€œtrain[s] future leadersโ€ is standardless.

Second, respondentsโ€™ admissions programs fail to articulate a meaningful connection between the means they employ and the goals they pursue. To achieve the educational benefits of diversity, respondents measure the racial composition of their classes using racial categories that are plainly overbroad (expressing, for example, no concern whether South Asian or East Asian students are adequately represented as โ€œAsianโ€); arbitrary or undefined (the use of the category โ€œHispanicโ€); or underinclusive (no category at all for Middle Eastern students). The unclear connection between the goals that respondents seek and the means they employ preclude courts from meaningfully scrutinizing respondentsโ€™ admissions programs.

The universitiesโ€™ main response to these criticisms is โ€œtrust us.โ€ They assert that universities are owed deference when using race to benefit some applicants but not others. While this Court has recognized a โ€œtradition of giving a degree of deference to a universityโ€™s academic decisions,โ€ it has made clear that deference must exist โ€œwithin constitutionally prescribed limits.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 328. Respondents have failed to present an exceedingly persuasive justification for separating students on the basis of race that is measurable and concrete enough to permit judicial review, as the Equal Protection Clause requires. Pp. 22โ€“26.

(2) Respondentsโ€™ race-based admissions systems also fail to comply with the Equal Protection Clauseโ€™s twin commands that race may never be used as a โ€œnegativeโ€ and that it may not operate as a stereotype. The First Circuit found that Harvardโ€™s consideration of race has resulted in fewer admissions of Asian-American students. Respondentsโ€™ assertion that race is never a negative factor in their admissions programs cannot withstand scrutiny. College admissions are zero-sum, and a benefit provided to some applicants but not to others necessarily advantages the former at the expense of the latter.

Respondentsโ€™ admissions programs are infirm for a second reason as well: They require stereotypingโ€”the very thing Grutter foreswore. When a university admits students โ€œon the basis of race, it engages in the offensive and demeaning assumption that [students] of a particular race, because of their race, think alike.โ€ Miller v. Johnson, 515 U. S. 900, 911โ€“912. Such stereotyping is contrary to the โ€œcore purposeโ€ of the Equal Protection Clause. Palmore, 466 U. S., at 432. Pp. 26โ€“29.

(3) Respondentsโ€™ admissions programs also lack a โ€œlogical end pointโ€ as Grutter required. 539 U. S., at 342. Respondents suggest that the end of race-based admissions programs will occur once meaningful representation and diversity are achieved on college campuses. Such measures of success amount to little more than comparing the racial breakdown of the incoming class and comparing it to some other metric, such as the racial makeup of the previous incoming class or the population in general, to see whether some proportional goal has been reached. The problem with this approach is well established: โ€œ[O]utright racial balancingโ€ is โ€œpatently unconstitutional.โ€ Fisher, 570 U. S., at 311. Respondentsโ€™ second proffered end pointโ€”when students receive the educational benefits of diversityโ€”fares no better. As explained, it is unclear how a court is supposed to determine if or when such goals would be adequately met. Third, respondents suggest the 25-year expectation in Grutter means that race-based preferences must be allowed to continue until at least 2028. The Courtโ€™s statement in Grutter, however, reflected only that Courtโ€™s expectation that race-based preferences would, by 2028, be unnecessary in the context of racial diversity on college campuses. Finally, respondents argue that the frequent reviews they conduct to determine whether racial preferences are still necessary obviates the need for an end point. But Grutter never suggested that periodic review can make unconstitutional conduct constitutional. Pp. 29โ€“34.

(f) Because Harvardโ€™s and UNCโ€™s admissions programs lack sufficiently focused and measurable objectives warranting the use of race, unavoidably employ race in a negative manner, involve racial stereotyping, and lack meaningful end points, those admissions programs cannot be reconciled with the guarantees of the Equal Protection Clause. At the same time, nothing prohibits universities from considering an applicantโ€™s discussion of how race affected the applicantโ€™s life, so long as that discussion is concretely tied to a quality of character or unique ability that the particular applicant can contribute to the university. Many universities have for too long wrongly concluded that the touchstone of an individualโ€™s identity is not challenges bested, skills built, or lessons learned, but the color of their skin. This Nationโ€™s constitutional history does not tolerate that choice. Pp. 39โ€“40.

No. 20โ€“1199, 980 F. 3d 157; No. 21โ€“707, 567 F. Supp. 3d 580, reversed.

Roberts, C. J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which Thomas, Alito, Gorsuch, Kavanaugh, and Barrett, JJ., joined. Thomas, J., filed a concurring opinion. Gorsuch, J., filed a concurring opinion, in which Thomas, J., joined. Kavanaugh, J., filed a concurring opinion. Sotomayor, J., filed a dissenting opinion, in which Kagan, J., joined, and in which Jackson, J., joined as it applies to No. 21โ€“707. Jackson, J., filed a dissenting opinion in No. 21โ€“707, in which Sotomayor and Kagan, JJ., joined. Jackson, J., took no part in the consideration or decision of the case in No. 20โ€“1199.

________________________________________

Notes

1 Together with No. 21โ€“707, Students for Fair Admissions, Inc. v. University of North Carolina et al., on certiorari before judgment to the United States Court of Appeals for the Fourth Circuit.

________________________________________

Opinion

NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication in the United States Reports. Readers are requested to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States, Washington, D. C. 20543, [email protected], of any typographical or other formal errors.

SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES

_________________

Nos. 20โ€“1199 and 21โ€“707

_________________

STUDENTS FOR FAIR ADMISSIONS, INC., PETITIONER

20โ€“1199 v.

PRESIDENT AND FELLOWS OF HARVARD COLLEGE

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the first circuit

STUDENTS FOR FAIR ADMISSIONS, INC., PETITIONER

21โ€“707 v.

UNIVERSITY OF NORTH CAROLINA, et al.

on writ of certiorari before judgment to the united states court of appeals for the fourth circuit

________________________________________

[June 29, 2023]

________________________________________

Chief Justice Roberts delivered the opinion of the Court.

In these cases we consider whether the admissions systems used by Harvard College and the University of North Carolina, two of the oldest institutions of higher learning in the United States, are lawful under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

I

A

Founded in 1636, Harvard College has one of the most selective application processes in the country. Over 60,000 people applied to the school last year; fewer than 2,000 were admitted. Gaining admission to Harvard is thus no easy feat. It can depend on having excellent grades, glowing recommendation letters, or overcoming significant adversity. See 980 F. 3d 157, 166โ€“169 (CA1 2020). It can also depend on your race.

The admissions process at Harvard works as follows. Every application is initially screened by a โ€œfirst reader,โ€ who assigns scores in six categories: academic, extracurricular, athletic, school support, personal, and overall. Ibid. A rating of โ€œ1โ€ is the best; a rating of โ€œ6โ€ the worst. Ibid. In the academic category, for example, a โ€œ1โ€ signifies โ€œnear-perfect standardized test scores and gradesโ€; in the extracurricular category, it indicates โ€œtruly unusual achievementโ€; and in the personal category, it denotes โ€œoutstandingโ€ attributes like maturity, integrity, leadership, kindness, and courage. Id., at 167โ€“168. A score of โ€œ1โ€ on the overall ratingโ€”a composite of the five other ratingsโ€”โ€œsignifies an exceptional candidate with >90% chance of admission.โ€ Id., at 169 (internal quotation marks omitted). In assigning the overall rating, the first readers โ€œcan and do take an applicantโ€™s race into account.โ€ Ibid.

Once the first read process is complete, Harvard convenes admissions subcommittees. Ibid. Each subcommittee meets for three to five days and evaluates all applicants from a particular geographic area. Ibid. The subcommittees are responsible for making recommendations to the full admissions committee. Id., at 169โ€“170. The subcommittees can and do take an applicantโ€™s race into account when making their recommendations. Id., at 170.

The next step of the Harvard process is the full committee meeting. The committee has 40 members, and its discussion centers around the applicants who have been recommended by the regional subcommittees. Ibid. At the beginning of the meeting, the committee discusses the relative breakdown of applicants by race. The โ€œgoal,โ€ according to Harvardโ€™s director of admissions, โ€œis to make sure that [Harvard does] not hav[e] a dramatic drop-offโ€ in minority admissions from the prior class. 2 App. in No. 20โ€“1199, pp. 744, 747โ€“748. Each applicant considered by the full committee is discussed one by one, and every member of the committee must vote on admission. 980 F. 3d, at 170. Only when an applicant secures a majority of the full committeeโ€™s votes is he or she tentatively accepted for admission. Ibid. At the end of the full committee meeting, the racial composition of the pool of tentatively admitted students is disclosed to the committee. Ibid.; 2 App. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 861.

The final stage of Harvardโ€™s process is called the โ€œlop,โ€ during which the list of tentatively admitted students is winnowed further to arrive at the final class. Any applicants that Harvard considers cutting at this stage are placed on a โ€œlop list,โ€ which contains only four pieces of information: legacy status, recruited athlete status, financial aid eligibility, and race. 980 F. 3d, at 170. The full committee decides as a group which students to lop. 397 F. Supp. 3d 126, 144 (Mass. 2019). In doing so, the committee can and does take race into account. Ibid. Once the lop process is complete, Harvardโ€™s admitted class is set. Ibid. In the Harvard admissions process, โ€œrace is a determinative tip forโ€ a significant percentage โ€œof all admitted African American and Hispanic applicants.โ€ Id., at 178.

B

Founded shortly after the Constitution was ratified, the University of North Carolina (UNC) prides itself on being the โ€œnationโ€™s first public university.โ€ 567 F. Supp. 3d 580, 588 (MDNC 2021). Like Harvard, UNCโ€™s โ€œadmissions process is highly selectiveโ€: In a typical year, the school โ€œreceives approximately 43,500 applications for its freshman class of 4,200.โ€ Id., at 595.

Every application the University receives is initially reviewed by one of approximately 40 admissions office readers, each of whom reviews roughly five applications per hour. Id., at 596, 598. Readers are required to consider โ€œ[r]ace and ethnicity . . . as one factorโ€ in their review. Id., at 597 (internal quotation marks omitted). Other factors include academic performance and rigor, standardized testing results, extracurricular involvement, essay quality, personal factors, and student background. Id., at 600. Readers are responsible for providing numerical ratings for the academic, extracurricular, personal, and essay categories. Ibid. During the years at issue in this litigation, underrepresented minority students were โ€œmore likely to score [highly] on their personal ratings than their white and Asian American peers,โ€ but were more likely to be โ€œrated lower by UNC readers on their academic program, academic performance, . . . extracurricular activities,โ€ and essays. Id., at 616โ€“617.

After assessing an applicantโ€™s materials along these lines, the reader โ€œformulates an opinion about whether the student should be offered admissionโ€ and then โ€œwrites a comment defending his or her recommended decision.โ€ Id., at 598 (internal quotation marks omitted). In making that decision, readers may offer students a โ€œplusโ€ based on their race, which โ€œmay be significant in an individual case.โ€ Id., at 601 (internal quotation marks omitted). The admissions decisions made by the first readers are, in most cases, โ€œprovisionally final.โ€ Students for Fair Admissions, Inc. v. University of N. C. at Chapel Hill, No. 1:14โ€“cvโ€“954 (MDNC, Nov. 9, 2020), ECF Doc. 225, p. 7, ยถ52.

Following the first read process, โ€œapplications then go to a process called โ€˜school group reviewโ€™ . . . where a committee composed of experienced staff members reviews every [initial] decision.โ€ 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 599. The review committee receives a report on each student which contains, among other things, their โ€œclass rank, GPA, and test scores; the ratings assigned to them by their initial readers; and their status as residents, legacies, or special recruits.โ€ Ibid. (footnote omitted). The review committee either approves or rejects each admission recommendation made by the first reader, after which the admissions decisions are finalized. Ibid. In making those decisions, the review committee may also consider the applicantโ€™s race. Id., at 607; 2 App. in No. 21โ€“707, p. 407.1

C

Petitioner, Students for Fair Admissions (SFFA), is a nonprofit organization founded in 2014 whose purpose is โ€œto defend human and civil rights secured by law, including the right of individuals to equal protection under the law.โ€ 980 F. 3d, at 164 (internal quotation marks omitted). In November 2014, SFFA filed separate lawsuits against Harvard College and the University of North Carolina, arguing that their race-based admissions programs violated, respectively, Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, 78 Stat. 252, 42 U. S. C. ยง2000d et seq., and the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.2 See 397 F. Supp. 3d, at 131โ€“132; 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 585โ€“586. The District Courts in both cases held bench trials to evaluate SFFAโ€™s claims. See 980 F. 3d, at 179; 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 588. Trial in the Harvard case lasted 15 days and included testimony from 30 witnesses, after which the Court concluded that Harvardโ€™s admissions program comported with our precedents on the use of race in college admissions. See 397 F. Supp. 3d, at 132, 183. The First Circuit affirmed that determination. See 980 F. 3d, at 204. Similarly, in the UNC case, the District Court concluded after an eight-day trial that UNCโ€™s admissions program was permissible under the Equal Protection Clause. 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 588, 666.

We granted certiorari in the Harvard case and certiorari before judgment in the UNC case. 595 U. S. ___ (2022).

II

Before turning to the merits, we must assure ourselves of our jurisdiction. See Summers v. Earth Island Institute, 555 U. S. 488, 499 (2009). UNC argues that SFFA lacks standing to bring its claims because it is not a โ€œgenuineโ€ membership organization. Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, pp. 23โ€“26. Every court to have considered this argument has rejected it, and so do we. See Students for Fair Admissions, Inc. v. University of Tex. at Austin, 37 F. 4th 1078, 1084โ€“1086, and n. 8 (CA5 2022) (collecting cases).

Article III of the Constitution limits โ€œ[t]he judicial power of the United Statesโ€ to โ€œcasesโ€ or โ€œcontroversies,โ€ ensuring that federal courts act only โ€œas a necessity in the determination of real, earnest and vitalโ€ disputes. Muskrat v. United States, 219 U. S. 346, 351, 359 (1911) (internal quotation marks omitted). โ€œTo state a case or controversy under Article III, a plaintiff must establish standing.โ€ Arizona Christian School Tuition Organization v. Winn, 563 U. S. 125, 133 (2011). That, in turn, requires a plaintiff to demonstrate that it has โ€œ(1) suffered an injury in fact, (2) that is fairly traceable to the challenged conduct of the defendant, and (3) that is likely to be redressed by a favorable judicial decision.โ€ Spokeo, Inc. v. Robins, 578 U. S. 330, 338 (2016).

In cases like these, where the plaintiff is an organization, the standing requirements of Article III can be satisfied in two ways. Either the organization can claim that it suffered an injury in its own right or, alternatively, it can assert โ€œstanding solely as the representative of its members.โ€ Warth v. Seldin, 422 U. S. 490, 511 (1975). The latter approach is known as representational or organizational standing. Ibid.; Summers, 555 U. S., at 497โ€“498. To invoke it, an organization must demonstrate that โ€œ(a) its members would otherwise have standing to sue in their own right; (b) the interests it seeks to protect are germane to the organizationโ€™s purpose; and (c) neither the claim asserted nor the relief requested requires the participation of individual members in the lawsuit.โ€ Hunt v. Washington State Apple Advertising Commโ€™n, 432 U. S. 333, 343 (1977).

Respondents do not contest that SFFA satisfies the three-part test for organizational standing articulated in Hunt, and like the courts below, we find no basis in the record to conclude otherwise. See 980 F. 3d, at 182โ€“184; 397 F. Supp. 3d, at 183โ€“184; No. 1:14โ€“cvโ€“954 (MDNC, Sept. 29, 2018), App. D to Pet. for Cert. in No. 21โ€“707, pp. 237โ€“245 (2018 DC Opinion). Respondents instead argue that SFFA was not a โ€œgenuine โ€˜membership organizationโ€™ โ€ when it filed suit, and thus that it could not invoke the doctrine of organizational standing in the first place. Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 24. According to respondents, our decision in Hunt established that groups qualify as genuine membership organizations only if they are controlled and funded by their members. And because SFFAโ€™s members did neither at the time this litigation commenced, respondentsโ€™ argument goes, SFFA could not represent its members for purposes of Article III standing. Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 24 (citing Hunt, 432 U. S., at 343).

Hunt involved the Washington State Apple Advertising Commission, a state agency whose purpose was to protect the local apple industry. The Commission brought suit challenging a North Carolina statute that imposed a labeling requirement on containers of apples sold in that State. The Commission argued that it had standing to challenge the requirement on behalf of Washingtonโ€™s apple industry. See id., at 336โ€“341. We recognized, however, that as a state agency, โ€œthe Commission [wa]s not a traditional voluntary membership organization . . . , for it ha[d] no members at all.โ€ Id., at 342. As a result, we could not easily apply the three-part test for organizational standing, which asks whether an organizationโ€™s members have standing. We nevertheless concluded that the Commission had standing because the apple growers and dealers it represented were effectively members of the Commission. Id., at 344. The growers and dealers โ€œalone elect[ed] the members of the Commission,โ€ โ€œalone . . . serve[d] on the Commission,โ€ and โ€œalone finance[d] its activitiesโ€โ€”they possessed, in other words, โ€œall of the indicia of membership.โ€ Ibid. The Commission was therefore a genuine membership organization in substance, if not in form. And it was โ€œclearlyโ€ entitled to rely on the doctrine of organizational standing under the three-part test recounted above. Id., at 343.

The indicia of membership analysis employed in Hunt has no applicability in these cases. Here, SFFA is indisputably a voluntary membership organization with identifiable membersโ€”it is not, as in Hunt, a state agency that concededly has no members. See 2018 DC Opinion 241โ€“242. As the First Circuit in the Harvard litigation observed, at the time SFFA filed suit, it was โ€œa validly incorporated 501(c)(3) nonprofit with forty-seven members who joined voluntarily to support its mission.โ€ 980 F. 3d, at 184. Meanwhile in the UNC litigation, SFFA represented four members in particularโ€”high school graduates who were denied admission to UNC. See 2018 DC Opinion 234. Those members filed declarations with the District Court stating โ€œthat they have voluntarily joined SFFA; they support its mission; they receive updates about the status of the case from SFFAโ€™s President; and they have had the opportunity to have input and direction on SFFAโ€™s case.โ€ Id., at 234โ€“235 (internal quotation marks omitted). Where, as here, an organization has identified members and represents them in good faith, our cases do not require further scrutiny into how the organization operates. Because SFFA complies with the standing requirements demanded of organizational plaintiffs in Hunt, its obligations under Article III are satisfied.

III

A

In the wake of the Civil War, Congress proposed and the States ratified the Fourteenth Amendment, providing that no State shall โ€œdeny to any person . . . the equal protection of the laws.โ€ Amdt. 14, ยง1. To its proponents, the Equal Protection Clause represented a โ€œfoundation[al] principleโ€โ€”โ€œthe absolute equality of all citizens of the United States politically and civilly before their own laws.โ€ Cong. Globe, 39th Cong., 1st Sess., 431 (1866) (statement of Rep. Bingham) (Cong. Globe). The Constitution, they were determined, โ€œshould not permit any distinctions of law based on race or color,โ€ Supp. Brief for United States on Reargument in Brown v. Board of Education, O. T. 1953, No. 1 etc., p. 41 (detailing the history of the adoption of the Equal Protection Clause), because any โ€œlaw which operates upon one man [should] operate equally upon all,โ€ Cong. Globe 2459 (statement of Rep. Stevens). As soon-to-be President James Garfield observed, the Fourteenth Amendment would hold โ€œover every American citizen, without regard to color, the protecting shield of law.โ€ Id., at 2462. And in doing so, said Senator Jacob Howard of Michigan, the Amendment would give โ€œto the humblest, the poorest, the most despised of the race the same rights and the same protection before the law as it gives to the most powerful, the most wealthy, or the most haughty.โ€ Id., at 2766. For โ€œ[w]ithout this principle of equal justice,โ€ Howard continued, โ€œthere is no republican government and none that is really worth maintaining.โ€ Ibid.

At first, this Court embraced the transcendent aims of the Equal Protection Clause. โ€œWhat is this,โ€ we said of the Clause in 1880, โ€œbut declaring that the law in the States shall be the same for the black as for the white; that all persons, whether colored or white, shall stand equal before the laws of the States?โ€ Strauder v. West Virginia, 100 U. S. 303, 307โ€“309. โ€œ[T]he broad and benign provisions of the Fourteenth Amendmentโ€ apply โ€œto all persons,โ€ we unanimously declared six years later; it is โ€œhostility to . . . race and nationalityโ€ โ€œwhich in the eye of the law is not justified.โ€ Yick Wo v. Hopkins, 118 U. S. 356, 368โ€“369, 373โ€“374 (1886); see also id., at 368 (applying the Clause to โ€œaliens and subjects of the Emperor of Chinaโ€); Truax v. Raich, 239 U. S. 33, 36 (1915) (โ€œa native of Austriaโ€); semble Strauder, 100 U. S., at 308โ€“309 (โ€œCeltic Irishmenโ€) (dictum).

Despite our early recognition of the broad sweep of the Equal Protection Clause, this Courtโ€”alongside the countryโ€”quickly failed to live up to the Clauseโ€™s core commitments. For almost a century after the Civil War, state-mandated segregation was in many parts of the Nation a regrettable norm. This Court played its own role in that ignoble history, allowing in Plessy v. Ferguson the separate but equal regime that would come to deface much of America. 163 U. S. 537 (1896). The aspirations of the framers of the Equal Protection Clause, โ€œ[v]irtually strangled in [their] infancy,โ€ would remain for too long only thatโ€”aspirations. J. Tussman & J. tenBroek, The Equal Protection of the Laws, 37 Cal. L. Rev. 341, 381 (1949).

After Plessy, โ€œAmerican courts . . . labored with the doctrine [of separate but equal] for over half a century.โ€ Brown v. Board of Education, 347 U. S. 483, 491 (1954). Some cases in this period attempted to curtail the perniciousness of the doctrine by emphasizing that it required States to provide black students educational opportunities equal toโ€”even if formally separate fromโ€”those enjoyed by white students. See, e.g., Missouri ex rel. Gaines v. Canada, 305 U. S. 337, 349โ€“350 (1938) (โ€œThe admissibility of laws separating the races in the enjoyment of privileges afforded by the State rests wholly upon the equality of the privileges which the laws give to the separated groups . . . .โ€). But the inherent folly of that approachโ€”of trying to derive equality from inequalityโ€”soon became apparent. As the Court subse quently recognized, even racial distinctions that were argued to have no palpable effect worked to subordinate the afflicted students. See, e.g., McLaurin v. Oklahoma State Regents for Higher Ed., 339 U. S. 637, 640โ€“642 (1950) (โ€œIt is said that the separations imposed by the State in this case are in form merely nominal. . . . But they signify that the State . . . sets [petitioner] apart from the other students.โ€). By 1950, the inevitable truth of the Fourteenth Amendment had thus begun to reemerge: Separate cannot be equal.

The culmination of this approach came finally in Brown v. Board of Education. In that seminal decision, we overturned Plessy for good and set firmly on the path of invalidating all de jure racial discrimination by the States and Federal Government. 347 U. S., at 494โ€“495. Brown concerned the permissibility of racial segregation in public schools. The school district maintained that such segregation was lawful because the schools provided to black students and white students were of roughly the same quality. But we held such segregation impermissible โ€œeven though the physical facilities and other โ€˜tangibleโ€™ factors may be equal.โ€ Id., at 493 (emphasis added). The mere act of separating โ€œchildren . . . because of their race,โ€ we explained, itself โ€œgenerate[d] a feeling of inferiority.โ€ Id., at 494.

The conclusion reached by the Brown Court was thus unmistakably clear: the right to a public education โ€œmust be made available to all on equal terms.โ€ Id., at 493. As the plaintiffs had argued, โ€œno State has any authority under the equal-protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment to use race as a factor in affording educational opportunities among its citizens.โ€ Tr. of Oral Arg. in Brown I, O. T. 1952, No. 8, p. 7 (Robert L. Carter, Dec. 9, 1952); see also Supp. Brief for Appellants on Reargument in Nos. 1, 2, and 4, and for Respondents in No. 10, in Brown v. Board of Education, O. T. 1953, p. 65 (โ€œThat the Constitution is color blind is our dedicated belief.โ€); post, at 39, n. 7 (Thomas, J., concurring). The Court reiterated that rule just one year later, holding that โ€œfull complianceโ€ with Brown required schools to admit students โ€œon a racially nondiscriminatory basis.โ€ Brown v. Board of Education, 349 U. S. 294, 300โ€“301 (1955). The time for making distinctions based on race had passed. Brown, the Court observed, โ€œdeclar[ed] the fundamental principle that racial discrimination in public education is unconstitutional.โ€ Id., at 298.

So too in other areas of life. Immediately after Brown, we began routinely affirming lower court decisions that invalidated all manner of race-based state action. In Gayle v. Browder, for example, we summarily affirmed a decision invalidating state and local laws that required segregation in busing. 352 U. S. 903 (1956) (per curiam). As the lower court explained, โ€œ[t]he equal protection clause requires equality of treatment before the law for all persons without regard to race or color.โ€ Browder v. Gayle, 142 F. Supp. 707, 715 (MD Ala. 1956). And in Mayor and City Council of Baltimore v. Dawson, we summarily affirmed a decision striking down racial segregation at public beaches and bathhouses maintained by the State of Maryland and the city of Baltimore. 350 U. S. 877 (1955) (per curiam). โ€œIt is obvious that racial segregation in recreational activities can no longer be sustained,โ€ the lower court observed. Dawson v. Mayor and City Council of Baltimore, 220 F. 2d 386, 387 (CA4 1955) (per curiam). โ€œ[T]he ideal of equality before the law which characterizes our institutionsโ€ demanded as much. Ibid.

In the decades that followed, this Court continued to vindicate the Constitutionโ€™s pledge of racial equality. Laws dividing parks and golf courses; neighborhoods and businesses; buses and trains; schools and juries were undone, all by a transformative promise โ€œstemming from our American ideal of fairnessโ€: โ€œ โ€˜the Constitution . . . forbids . . . discrimination by the General Government, or by the States, against any citizen because of his race.โ€™ โ€ Bolling v. Sharpe, 347 U. S. 497, 499 (1954) (quoting Gibson v. Mississippi, 162 U. S. 565, 591 (1896) (Harlan, J., for the Court)). As we recounted in striking down the State of Virginiaโ€™s ban on interracial marriage 13 years after Brown, the Fourteenth Amendment โ€œproscri[bes] . . . all invidious racial discriminations.โ€ Loving v. Virginia, 388 U. S. 1, 8 (1967). Our cases had thus โ€œconsistently denied the constitutionality of measures which restrict the rights of citizens on account of race.โ€ Id., at 11โ€“12; see also Yick Wo, 118 U. S., at 373โ€“375 (commercial property); Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U. S. 1 (1948) (housing covenants); Hernandez v. Texas, 347 U. S. 475 (1954) (composition of juries); Dawson, 350 U. S., at 877 (beaches and bathhouses); Holmes v. Atlanta, 350 U. S. 879 (1955) (per curiam) (golf courses); Browder, 352 U. S., at 903 (busing); New Orleans City Park Improvement Assn. v. Detiege, 358 U. S. 54 (1958) (per curiam) (public parks); Bailey v. Patterson, 369 U. S. 31 (1962) (per curiam) (transportation facilities); Swann v. Charlotte-Mecklenburg Bd. of Ed., 402 U. S. 1 (1971) (education); Batson v. Kentucky, 476 U. S. 79 (1986) (peremptory jury strikes).

These decisions reflect the โ€œcore purposeโ€ of the Equal Protection Clause: โ€œdo[ing] away with all governmentally imposed discrimination based on race.โ€ Palmore v. Sidoti, 466 U. S. 429, 432 (1984) (footnote omitted). We have recognized that repeatedly. โ€œThe clear and central purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment was to eliminate all official state sources of invidious racial discrimination in the States.โ€ Loving, 388 U. S., at 10; see also Washington v. Davis, 426 U. S. 229, 239 (1976) (โ€œThe central purpose of the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment is the prevention of official conduct discriminating on the basis of race.โ€); McLaughlin v. Florida, 379 U. S. 184, 192 (1964) (โ€œ[T]he historical fact [is] that the central purpose of the Fourteenth Amendment was to eliminate racial discrimination.โ€).

Eliminating racial discrimination means eliminating all of it. And the Equal Protection Clause, we have accordingly held, applies โ€œwithout regard to any differences of race, of color, or of nationalityโ€โ€”it is โ€œuniversal in [its] application.โ€ Yick Wo, 118 U. S., at 369. For โ€œ[t]he guarantee of equal protection cannot mean one thing when applied to one individual and something else when applied to a person of another color.โ€ Regents of Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U. S. 265, 289โ€“290 (1978) (opinion of Powell, J.). โ€œIf both are not accorded the same protection, then it is not equal.โ€ Id., at 290.

Any exception to the Constitutionโ€™s demand for equal protection must survive a daunting two-step examination known in our cases as โ€œstrict scrutiny.โ€ Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Peรฑa, 515 U. S. 200, 227 (1995). Under that standard we ask, first, whether the racial classification is used to โ€œfurther compelling governmental interests.โ€ Grutter v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 306, 326 (2003). Second, if so, we ask whether the governmentโ€™s use of race is โ€œnarrowly tailoredโ€โ€”meaning โ€œnecessaryโ€โ€”to achieve that interest. Fisher v. University of Tex. at Austin, 570 U. S. 297, 311โ€“312 (2013) (Fisher I) (internal quotation marks omitted).

Outside the circumstances of these cases, our precedents have identified only two compelling interests that permit resort to race-based government action. One is remediating specific, identified instances of past discrimination that violated the Constitution or a statute. See, e.g., Parents Involved in Community Schools v. Seattle School Dist. No. 1, 551 U. S. 701, 720 (2007); Shaw v. Hunt, 517 U. S. 899, 909โ€“910 (1996); post, at 19โ€“20, 30โ€“31 (opinion of Thomas, J.). The second is avoiding imminent and serious risks to human safety in prisons, such as a race riot. See Johnson v. California, 543 U. S. 499, 512โ€“513 (2005).

Our acceptance of race-based state action has been rare for a reason. โ€œDistinctions between citizens solely because of their ancestry are by their very nature odious to a free people whose institutions are founded upon the doctrine of equality.โ€ Rice v. Cayetano, 528 U. S. 495, 517 (2000) (quoting Hirabayashi v. United States, 320 U. S. 81, 100 (1943)). That principle cannot be overridden except in the most extraordinary case.

B

These cases involve whether a university may make admissions decisions that turn on an applicantโ€™s race. Our Court first considered that issue in Regents of University of California v. Bakke, which involved a set-aside admissions program used by the University of California, Davis, medical school. 438 U. S., at 272โ€“276. Each year, the school held 16 of its 100 seats open for members of certain minority groups, who were reviewed on a special admissions track separate from those in the main admissions pool. Id., at 272โ€“275. The plaintiff, Allan Bakke, was denied admission two years in a row, despite the admission of minority applicants with lower grade point averages and MCAT scores. Id., at 276โ€“277. Bakke subsequently sued the school, arguing that its set-aside program violated the Equal Protection Clause.

In a deeply splintered decision that produced six different opinionsโ€”none of which commanded a majority of the Courtโ€”we ultimately ruled in part in favor of the school and in part in favor of Bakke. Justice Powell announced the Courtโ€™s judgment, and his opinionโ€”though written for himself aloneโ€”would eventually come to โ€œserv[e] as the touchstone for constitutional analysis of race-conscious admissions policies.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 323.

Justice Powell began by finding three of the schoolโ€™s four justifications for its policy not sufficiently compelling. The schoolโ€™s first justification of โ€œreducing the historic deficit of traditionally disfavored minorities in medical schools,โ€ he wrote, was akin to โ€œ[p]referring members of any one group for no reason other than race or ethnic origin.โ€ Bakke, 438 U. S., at 306โ€“307 (internal quotation marks omitted). Yet that was โ€œdiscrimination for its own sake,โ€ which โ€œthe Constitution forbids.โ€ Id., at 307 (citing, inter alia, Loving, 388 U. S., at 11). Justice Powell next observed that the goal of โ€œremedying . . . the effects of โ€˜societal discriminationโ€™ โ€ was also insufficient because it was โ€œan amorphous concept of injury that may be ageless in its reach into the past.โ€ Bakke, 438 U. S., at 307. Finally, Justice Powell found there was โ€œvirtually no evidence in the record indicating that [the schoolโ€™s] special admissions programโ€ would, as the school had argued, increase the number of doctors working in underserved areas. Id., at 310.

Justice Powell then turned to the schoolโ€™s last interest asserted to be compellingโ€”obtaining the educational benefits that flow from a racially diverse student body. That interest, in his view, was โ€œa constitutionally permissible goal for an institution of higher education.โ€ Id., at 311โ€“312. And that was so, he opined, because a university was entitled as a matter of academic freedom โ€œto make its own judgments as to . . . the selection of its student body.โ€ Id., at 312.

But a universityโ€™s freedom was not unlimited. โ€œRacial and ethnic distinctions of any sort are inherently suspect,โ€ Justice Powell explained, and antipathy toward them was deeply โ€œrooted in our Nationโ€™s constitutional and demographic history.โ€ Id., at 291. A university could not employ a quota system, for example, reserving โ€œa specified number of seats in each class for individuals from the preferred ethnic groups.โ€ Id., at 315. Nor could it impose a โ€œmultitrack program with a prescribed number of seats set aside for each identifiable category of applicants.โ€ Ibid. And neither still could it use race to foreclose an individual โ€œfrom all consideration . . . simply because he was not the right color.โ€ Id., at 318.

The role of race had to be cabined. It could operate only as โ€œa โ€˜plusโ€™ in a particular applicantโ€™s file.โ€ Id., at 317. And even then, race was to be weighed in a manner โ€œflexible enough to consider all pertinent elements of diversity in light of the particular qualifications of each applicant.โ€ Ibid. Justice Powell derived this approach from what he called the โ€œilluminating exampleโ€ of the admissions system then used by Harvard College. Id., at 316. Under that system, as described by Harvard in a brief it had filed with the Court, โ€œthe race of an applicant may tip the balance in his favor just as geographic origin or a life [experience] may tip the balance in other candidatesโ€™ cases.โ€ Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). Harvard continued: โ€œA farm boy from Idaho can bring something to Harvard College that a Bostonian cannot offer. Similarly, a black student can usually bring something that a white person cannot offer.โ€ Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). The result, Harvard proclaimed, was that โ€œrace has beenโ€โ€”and should beโ€”โ€œa factor in some admission decisions.โ€ Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted).

No other Member of the Court joined Justice Powellโ€™s opinion. Four Justices instead would have held that the government may use race for the purpose of โ€œremedying the effects of past societal discrimination.โ€ Id., at 362 (joint opinion of Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part). Four other Justices, meanwhile, would have struck down the Davis program as violative of Title VI. In their view, it โ€œseem[ed] clear that the proponents of Title VI assumed that the Constitution itself required a colorblind standard on the part of government.โ€ Id., at 416 (Stevens, J., joined by Burger, C. J., and Stewart and Rehnquist, JJ., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part). The Davis program therefore flatly contravened a core โ€œprinciple imbedded in the constitutional and moral understanding of the timesโ€: the prohibition against โ€œracial discrimination.โ€ Id., at 418, n. 21 (internal quotation marks omitted).

C

In the years that followed our โ€œfractured decision in Bakke,โ€ lower courts โ€œstruggled to discern whether Justice Powellโ€™sโ€ opinion constituted โ€œbinding precedent.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 325. We accordingly took up the matter again in 2003, in the case Grutter v. Bollinger, which concerned the admissions system used by the University of Michigan law school. Id., at 311. There, in another sharply divided decision, the Court for the first time โ€œendorse[d] Justice Powellโ€™s view that student body diversity is a compelling state interest that can justify the use of race in university admissions.โ€ Id., at 325.

The Courtโ€™s analysis tracked Justice Powellโ€™s in many respects. As for compelling interest, the Court held that โ€œ[t]he Law Schoolโ€™s educational judgment that such diversity is essential to its educational mission is one to which we defer.โ€ Id., at 328. In achieving that goal, however, the Court made clearโ€”just as Justice Powell hadโ€”that the law school was limited in the means that it could pursue. The school could not โ€œestablish quotas for members of certain racial groups or put members of those groups on separate admissions tracks.โ€ Id., at 334. Neither could it โ€œinsulate applicants who belong to certain racial or ethnic groups from the competition for admission.โ€ Ibid. Nor still could it desire โ€œsome specified percentage of a particular group merely because of its race or ethnic origin.โ€ Id., at 329โ€“330 (quoting Bakke, 438 U. S., at 307 (opinion of Powell, J.)).

These limits, Grutter explained, were intended to guard against two dangers that all race-based government action portends. The first is the risk that the use of race will devolve into โ€œillegitimate . . . stereotyp[ing].โ€ Richmond v. J. A. Croson Co., 488 U. S. 469, 493 (1989) (plurality opinion). Universities were thus not permitted to operate their admissions programs on the โ€œbelief that minority students always (or even consistently) express some characteristic minority viewpoint on any issue.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 333 (internal quotation marks omitted). The second risk is that race would be used not as a plus, but as a negativeโ€”to discriminate against those racial groups that were not the beneficiaries of the race-based preference. A universityโ€™s use of race, accordingly, could not occur in a manner that โ€œunduly harm[ed] nonminority applicants.โ€ Id., at 341.

But even with these constraints in place, Grutter expressed marked discomfort with the use of race in college admissions. The Court stressed the fundamental principle that โ€œthere are serious problems of justice connected with the idea of [racial] preference itself.โ€ Ibid. (quoting Bakke, 438 U. S., at 298 (opinion of Powell, J.)). It observed that all โ€œracial classifications, however compelling their goals,โ€ were โ€œdangerous.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 342. And it cautioned that all โ€œrace-based governmental actionโ€ should โ€œremai[n] subject to continuing oversight to assure that it will work the least harm possible to other innocent persons competing for the benefit.โ€ Id., at 341 (internal quotation marks omitted).

To manage these concerns, Grutter imposed one final limit on race-based admissions programs. At some point, the Court held, they must end. Id., at 342. This requirement was critical, and Grutter emphasized it repeatedly. โ€œ[A]ll race-conscious admissions programs [must] have a termination pointโ€; they โ€œmust have reasonable durational limitsโ€; they โ€œmust be limited in timeโ€; they must have โ€œsunset provisionsโ€; they โ€œmust have a logical end pointโ€; their โ€œdeviation from the norm of equal treatmentโ€ must be โ€œa temporary matter.โ€ Ibid. (internal quotation marks omitted). The importance of an end point was not just a matter of repetition. It was the reason the Court was willing to dispense temporarily with the Constitutionโ€™s unambiguous guarantee of equal protection. The Court recognized as much: โ€œ[e]nshrining a permanent justification for racial preferences,โ€ the Court explained, โ€œwould offend this fundamental equal protection principle.โ€ Ibid.; see also id., at 342โ€“343 (quoting N. Nathanson & C. Bartnik, The Constitutionality of Preferential Treatment for Minority Applicants to Professional Schools, 58 Chi. Bar Rec. 282, 293 (Mayโ€“June 1977), for the proposition that โ€œ[i]t would be a sad day indeed, were America to become a quota-ridden society, with each identifiable minority assigned proportional representation in every desirable walk of lifeโ€).

Grutter thus concluded with the following caution: โ€œIt has been 25 years since Justice Powell first approved the use of race to further an interest in student body diversity in the context of public higher education. . . . We expect that 25 years from now, the use of racial preferences will no longer be necessary to further the interest approved today.โ€ 539 U. S., at 343.

IV

Twenty years later, no end is in sight. โ€œHarvardโ€™s view about when [race-based admissions will end] doesnโ€™t have a date on it.โ€ Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 20โ€“1199, p. 85; Brief for Respondent in No. 20โ€“1199, p. 52. Neither does UNCโ€™s. 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 612. Yet both insist that the use of race in their admissions programs must continue.

But we have permitted race-based admissions only within the confines of narrow restrictions. University programs must comply with strict scrutiny, they may never use race as a stereotype or negative, andโ€”at some pointโ€”they must end. Respondentsโ€™ admissions systemsโ€”however well intentioned and implemented in good faithโ€”fail each of these criteria. They must therefore be invalidated under the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.

A

Because โ€œ[r]acial discrimination [is] invidious in all contexts,โ€ Edmonson v. Leesville Concrete Co., 500 U. S. 614, 619 (1991), we have required that universities operate their race-based admissions programs in a manner that is โ€œsufficiently measurable to permit judicial [review]โ€ under the rubric of strict scrutiny, Fisher v. University of Tex. at Austin, 579 U. S. 365, 381 (2016) (Fisher II). โ€œClassifying and assigningโ€ students based on their race โ€œrequires more than . . . an amorphous end to justify it.โ€ Parents Involved, 551 U. S., at 735.

Respondents have fallen short of satisfying that burden. First, the interests they view as compelling cannot be subjected to meaningful judicial review. Harvard identifies the following educational benefits that it is pursuing: (1) โ€œtraining future leaders in the public and private sectorsโ€; (2) preparing graduates to โ€œadapt to an increasingly pluralistic societyโ€; (3) โ€œbetter educating its students through diversityโ€; and (4) โ€œproducing new knowledge stemming from diverse outlooks.โ€ 980 F. 3d, at 173โ€“174. UNC points to similar benefits, namely, โ€œ(1) promoting the robust exchange of ideas; (2) broadening and refining understanding; (3) fostering innovation and problem-solving; (4) preparing engaged and productive citizens and leaders; [and] (5) enhancing appreciation, respect, and empathy, cross-racial understanding, and breaking down stereotypes.โ€ 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 656.

Although these are commendable goals, they are not sufficiently coherent for purposes of strict scrutiny. At the outset, it is unclear how courts are supposed to measure any of these goals. How is a court to know whether leaders have been adequately โ€œtrain[ed]โ€; whether the exchange of ideas is โ€œrobustโ€; or whether โ€œnew knowledgeโ€ is being developed? Ibid.; 980 F. 3d, at 173โ€“174. Even if these goals could somehow be measured, moreover, how is a court to know when they have been reached, and when the perilous remedy of racial preferences may cease? There is no particular point at which there exists sufficient โ€œinnovation and problem-solving,โ€ or students who are appropriately โ€œengaged and productive.โ€ 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 656. Finally, the question in this context is not one of no diversity or of some: it is a question of degree. How many fewer leaders Harvard would create without racial preferences, or how much poorer the education at Harvard would be, are inquiries no court could resolve.

Comparing respondentsโ€™ asserted goals to interests we have recognized as compelling further illustrates their elusive nature. In the context of racial violence in a prison, for example, courts can ask whether temporary racial segregation of inmates will prevent harm to those in the prison. See Johnson, 543 U. S., at 512โ€“513. When it comes to workplace discrimination, courts can ask whether a race-based benefit makes members of the discriminated class โ€œwhole for [the] injuries [they] suffered.โ€ Franks v. Bowman Transp. Co., 424 U. S. 747, 763 (1976) (internal quotation marks omitted). And in school segregation cases, courts can determine whether any race-based remedial action produces a distribution of students โ€œcompar[able] to what it would have been in the absence of such constitutional violations.โ€ Dayton Bd. of Ed. v. Brinkman, 433 U. S. 406, 420 (1977).

Nothing like that is possible when it comes to evaluating the interests respondents assert here. Unlike discerning whether a prisoner will be injured or whether an employee should receive backpay, the question whether a particular mix of minority students produces โ€œengaged and productive citizens,โ€ sufficiently โ€œenhance[s] appreciation, respect, and empathy,โ€ or effectively โ€œtrain[s] future leadersโ€ is standardless. 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 656; 980 F. 3d, at 173โ€“174. The interests that respondents seek, though plainly worthy, are inescapably imponderable.

Second, respondentsโ€™ admissions programs fail to articulate a meaningful connection between the means they employ and the goals they pursue. To achieve the educational benefits of diversity, UNC works to avoid the underrepresentation of minority groups, 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 591โ€“592, and n. 7, while Harvard likewise โ€œguard[s ] against inadvertent drop-offs in representationโ€ of certain minority groups from year to year, Brief for Respondent in No. 20โ€“1199, at 16. To accomplish both of those goals, in turn, the universities measure the racial composition of their classes using the following categories: (1) Asian; (2) Native Hawaiian or Pacific Islander; (3) Hispanic; (4) White; (5) African-American; and (6) Native American. See, e.g., 397 F. Supp. 3d, at 137, 178; 3 App. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 1278, 1280โ€“1283; 3 App. in No. 21โ€“707, at 1234โ€“1241. It is far from evident, though, how assigning students to these racial categories and making admissions decisions based on them furthers the educational benefits that the universities claim to pursue.

For starters, the categories are themselves imprecise in many ways. Some of them are plainly overbroad: by grouping together all Asian students, for instance, respondents are apparently uninterested in whether South Asian or East Asian students are adequately represented, so long as there is enough of one to compensate for a lack of the other. Meanwhile other racial categories, such as โ€œHispanic,โ€ are arbitrary or undefined. See, e.g., M. Lopez, J. Krogstad, & J. Passel, Pew Research Center, Who is Hispanic? (Sept. 15, 2022) (referencing the โ€œlong history of changing labels [and] shifting categories . . . reflect[ing] evolving cultural norms about what it means to be Hispanic or Latino in the U. S. todayโ€). And still other categories are underinclusive. When asked at oral argument โ€œhow are applicants from Middle Eastern countries classified, [such as] Jordan, Iraq, Iran, [and] Egypt,โ€ UNCโ€™s counsel responded, โ€œ[I] do not know the answer to that question.โ€ Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 21โ€“707, p. 107; cf. post, at 6โ€“7 (Gorsuch, J., concurring) (detailing the โ€œincoherentโ€ and โ€œirrational stereotypesโ€ that these racial categories further).

Indeed, the use of these opaque racial categories undermines, instead of promotes, respondentsโ€™ goals. By focusing on underrepresentation, respondents would apparently prefer a class with 15% of students from Mexico over a class with 10% of students from several Latin American countries, simply because the former contains more Hispanic students than the latter. Yet โ€œ[i]t is hard to understand how a plan that could allow these results can be viewed as being concerned with achieving enrollment that is โ€˜broadly diverse.โ€™ โ€ Parents Involved, 551 U. S., at 724 (quoting Grutter, 539 U. S., at 329). And given the mismatch between the means respondents employ and the goals they seek, it is especially hard to understand how courts are supposed to scrutinize the admissions programs that respondents use.

The universitiesโ€™ main response to these criticisms is, essentially, โ€œtrust us.โ€ None of the questions recited above need answering, they say, because universities are โ€œowed deferenceโ€ when using race to benefit some applicants but not others. Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 39 (internal quotation marks omitted). It is true that our cases have recognized a โ€œtradition of giving a degree of deference to a universityโ€™s academic decisions.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 328. But we have been unmistakably clear that any deference must exist โ€œwithin constitutionally prescribed limits,โ€ ibid., and that โ€œdeference does not imply abandonment or abdication of judicial review,โ€ Millerโ€“El v. Cockrell, 537 U. S. 322, 340 (2003). Universities may define their missions as they see fit. The Constitution defines ours. Courts may not license separating students on the basis of race without an exceedingly persuasive justification that is measurable and concrete enough to permit judicial review. As this Court has repeatedly reaffirmed, โ€œ[r]acial classifications are simply too pernicious to permit any but the most exact connection between justification and classification.โ€ Gratz v. Bollinger, 539 U. S. 244, 270 (2003) (internal quotation marks omitted). The programs at issue here do not satisfy that standard.

B

The race-based admissions systems that respondents employ also fail to comply with the twin commands of the Equal Protection Clause that race may never be used as a โ€œnegativeโ€ and that it may not operate as a stereotype.

First, our cases have stressed that an individualโ€™s race may never be used against him in the admissions process. Here, however, the First Circuit found that Harvardโ€™s consideration of race has led to an 11.1% decrease in the number of Asian-Americans admitted to Harvard. 980 F. 3d, at 170, n. 29. And the District Court observed that Harvardโ€™s โ€œpolicy of considering applicantsโ€™ race . . . overall results in fewer Asian American and white students being admitted.โ€ 397 F. Supp. 3d, at 178.

Respondents nonetheless contend that an individualโ€™s race is never a negative factor in their admissions programs, but that assertion cannot withstand scrutiny. Harvard, for example, draws an analogy between race and other factors it considers in admission. โ€œ[W]hile admissions officers may give a preference to applicants likely to excel in the Harvard-Radcliffe Orchestra,โ€ Harvard explains, โ€œthat does not mean it is a โ€˜negativeโ€™ not to excel at a musical instrument.โ€ Brief for Respondent in No. 20โ€“1199, at 51. But on Harvardโ€™s logic, while it gives preferences to applicants with high grades and test scores, โ€œthat does not mean it is a โ€˜negativeโ€™ โ€ to be a student with lower grades and lower test scores. Ibid. This understanding of the admissions process is hard to take seriously. College admissions are zero-sum. A benefit provided to some applicants but not to others necessarily advantages the former group at the expense of the latter.

Respondents also suggest that race is not a negative factor because it does not impact many admissions decisions. See id., at 49; Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 2. Yet, at the same time, respondents also maintain that the demographics of their admitted classes would meaningfully change if race-based admissions were abandoned. And they acknowledge that race is determinative for at least someโ€”if not manyโ€”of the students they admit. See, e.g., Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 67; 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 633. How else but โ€œnegativeโ€ can race be described if, in its absence, members of some racial groups would be admitted in greater numbers than they otherwise would have been? The โ€œ[e]qual protection of the laws is not achieved through indiscriminate imposition of inequalities.โ€ Shelley, 334 U. S., at 22.6

Respondentsโ€™ admissions programs are infirm for a second reason as well. We have long held that universities may not operate their admissions programs on the โ€œbelief that minority students always (or even consistently) express some characteristic minority viewpoint on any issue.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 333 (internal quotation marks omitted). That requirement is found throughout our Equal Protection Clause jurisprudence more generally. See, e.g., Schuette v. BAMN, 572 U. S. 291, 308 (2014) (plurality opinion) (โ€œIn cautioning against โ€˜impermissible racial stereotypes,โ€™ this Court has rejected the assumption that โ€˜members of the same racial groupโ€”regardless of their age, education, economic status, or the community in which they liveโ€”think alike . . . .โ€™ โ€ (quoting Shaw v. Reno, 509 U. S. 630, 647 (1993))).

Yet by accepting race-based admissions programs in which some students may obtain preferences on the basis of race alone, respondentsโ€™ programs tolerate the very thing that Grutter foreswore: stereotyping. The point of respondentsโ€™ admissions programs is that there is an inherent benefit in race qua raceโ€”in race for raceโ€™s sake. Respondents admit as much. Harvardโ€™s admissions process rests on the pernicious stereotype that โ€œa black student can usually bring something that a white person cannot offer.โ€ Bakke, 438 U. S., at 316 (opinion of Powell, J.) (internal quotation marks omitted); see also Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 92. UNC is much the same. It argues that race in itself โ€œsays [something] about who you are.โ€ Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 21โ€“707, at 97; see also id., at 96 (analogizing being of a certain race to being from a rural area).

We have time and again forcefully rejected the notion that government actors may intentionally allocate preference to those โ€œwho may have little in common with one another but the color of their skin.โ€ Shaw, 509 U. S., at 647. The entire point of the Equal Protection Clause is that treating someone differently because of their skin color is not like treating them differently because they are from a city or from a suburb, or because they play the violin poorly or well.

โ€œOne of the principal reasons race is treated as a forbidden classification is that it demeans the dignity and worth of a person to be judged by ancestry instead of by his or her own merit and essential qualities.โ€ Rice, 528 U. S., at 517. But when a university admits students โ€œon the basis of race, it engages in the offensive and demeaning assumption that [students] of a particular race, because of their race, think alike,โ€ Miller v. Johnson, 515 U. S. 900, 911โ€“912 (1995) (internal quotation marks omitted)โ€”at the very least alike in the sense of being different from nonminority students. In doing so, the university furthers โ€œstereotypes that treat individuals as the product of their race, evaluating their thoughts and effortsโ€”their very worth as citizensโ€”according to a criterion barred to the Government by history and the Constitution.โ€ Id., at 912 (internal quotation marks omitted). Such stereotyping can only โ€œcause[ ] continued hurt and injury,โ€ Edmonson, 500 U. S., at 631, contrary as it is to the โ€œcore purposeโ€ of the Equal Protection Clause, Palmore, 466 U. S., at 432.

C

If all this were not enough, respondentsโ€™ admissions programs also lack a โ€œlogical end point.โ€ Grutter, 539 U. S., at 342.

Respondents and the Government first suggest that respondentsโ€™ race-based admissions programs will end when, in their absence, there is โ€œmeaningful representation and meaningful diversityโ€ on college campuses. Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 21โ€“707, at 167. The metric of meaningful representation, respondents assert, does not involve any โ€œstrict numerical benchmark,โ€ id., at 86; or โ€œprecise number or percentage,โ€ id., at 167; or โ€œspecified percentage,โ€ Brief for Respondent in No. 20โ€“1199, at 38 (internal quotation marks omitted). So what does it involve?

Numbers all the same. At Harvard, each full committee meeting begins with a discussion of โ€œhow the breakdown of the class compares to the prior year in terms of racial identities.โ€ 397 F. Supp. 3d, at 146. And โ€œif at some point in the admissions process it appears that a group is notably underrepresented or has suffered a dramatic drop off relative to the prior year, the Admissions Committee may decide to give additional attention to applications from students within that group.โ€ Ibid.; see also id., at 147 (District Court finding that Harvard uses race to โ€œtrac[k] how each class is shaping up relative to previous years with an eye towards achieving a level of racial diversityโ€); 2 App. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 821โ€“822.

The results of the Harvard admissions process reflect this numerical commitment. For the admitted classes of 2009 to 2018, black students represented a tight band of 10.0%โ€“11.7% of the admitted pool. The same theme held true for other minority groups:

Brief for Petitioner in No. 20โ€“1199 etc., p. 23. Harvardโ€™s focus on numbers is obvious.

UNCโ€™s admissions program operates similarly. The University frames the challenge it faces as โ€œthe admission and enrollment of underrepresented minorities,โ€ Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 7, a metric that turns solely on whether a groupโ€™s โ€œpercentage enrollment within the undergraduate student body is lower than their percentage within the general population in North Carolina,โ€ 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 591, n. 7; see also Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 21โ€“707, at 79. The University โ€œhas not yet fully achieved its diversity-related educational goals,โ€ it explains, in part due to its failure to obtain closer to proportional representation. Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 7; see also 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 594.

The problem with these approaches is well established. โ€œ[O]utright racial balancingโ€ is โ€œpatently unconstitutional.โ€ Fisher I, 570 U. S., at 311 (internal quotation marks omitted). That is so, we have repeatedly explained, because โ€œ[a]t the heart of the Constitutionโ€™s guarantee of equal protection lies the simple command that the Government must treat citizens as individuals, not as simply components of a racial, religious, sexual or national class.โ€ Miller, 515 U. S., at 911 (internal quotation marks omitted). By promising to terminate their use of race only when some rough percentage of various racial groups is admitted, respondents turn that principle on its head. Their admissions programs โ€œeffectively assure[ ] that race will always be relevant . . . and that the ultimate goal of eliminatingโ€ race as a criterion โ€œwill never be achieved.โ€ Croson, 488 U. S., at 495 (internal quotation marks omitted).

Respondentsโ€™ second proffered end point fares no better. Respondents assert that universities will no longer need to engage in race-based admissions when, in their absence, students nevertheless receive the educational benefits of diversity. But as we have already explained, it is not clear how a court is supposed to determine when stereotypes have broken down or โ€œproductive citizens and leadersโ€ have been created. 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 656. Nor is there any way to know whether those goals would adequately be met in the absence of a race-based admissions program. As UNC itself acknowledges, these โ€œqualitative standard[s]โ€ are โ€œdifficult to measure.โ€ Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 21โ€“707, at 78; but see Fisher II, 579 U. S., at 381 (requiring race-based admissions programs to operate in a manner that is โ€œsufficiently measurableโ€).

Third, respondents suggest that race-based preferences must be allowed to continue for at least five more years, based on the Courtโ€™s statement in Grutter that it โ€œexpect[ed] that 25 years from now, the use of racial preferences will no longer be necessary.โ€ 539 U. S., at 343. The 25-year mark articulated in Grutter, however, reflected only that Courtโ€™s view that race-based preferences would, by 2028, be unnecessary to ensure a requisite level of racial diversity on college campuses. Ibid. That expectation was oversold. Neither Harvard nor UNC believes that race-based admissions will in fact be unnecessary in five years, and both universities thus expect to continue using race as a criterion well beyond the time limit that Grutter suggested. See Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 84โ€“85; Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 21โ€“707, at 85โ€“86. Indeed, the high school applicants that Harvard and UNC will evaluate this fall using their race-based admissions systems are expected to graduate in 2028โ€”25 years after Grutter was decided.

Finally, respondents argue that their programs need not have an end point at all because they frequently review them to determine whether they remain necessary. See Brief for Respondent in No. 20โ€“1199, at 52; Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 58โ€“59. Respondents point to language in Grutter that, they contend, permits โ€œthe durational requirement [to] be metโ€ with โ€œperiodic reviews to determine whether racial preferences are still necessary to achieve student body diversity.โ€ 539 U. S., at 342. But Grutter never suggested that periodic review could make unconstitutional conduct constitutional. To the contrary, the Court made clear that race-based admissions programs eventually had to endโ€”despite whatever periodic review universities conducted. Ibid.; see also supra, at 18.

Here, however, Harvard concedes that its race-based admissions program has no end point. Brief for Respondent in No. 20โ€“1199, at 52 (Harvard โ€œhas not set a sunset dateโ€ for its program (internal quotation marks omitted)). And it acknowledges that the way it thinks about the use of race in its admissions process โ€œis the same now as it wasโ€ nearly 50 years ago. Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 91. UNCโ€™s race-based admissions program is likewise not set to expire any time soonโ€”nor, indeed, any time at all. The University admits that it โ€œhas not set forth a proposed time period in which it believes it can end all race-conscious admissions practices.โ€ 567 F. Supp. 3d, at 612. And UNC suggests that it might soon use race to a greater extent than it currently does. See Brief for University Respondents in No. 21โ€“707, at 57. In short, there is no reason to believe that respondents willโ€”even acting in good faithโ€”comply with the Equal Protection Clause any time soon.

V

The dissenting opinions resist these conclusions. They would instead uphold respondentsโ€™ admissions programs based on their view that the Fourteenth Amendment permits state actors to remedy the effects of societal discrimination through explicitly race-based measures. Although both opinions are thorough and thoughtful in many respects, this Court has long rejected their core thesis.

The dissentsโ€™ interpretation of the Equal Protection Clause is not new. In Bakke, four Justices would have permitted race-based admissions programs to remedy the effects of societal discrimination. 438 U. S., at 362 (joint opinion of Brennan, White, Marshall, and Blackmun, JJ., concurring in judgment in part and dissenting in part). But that minority view was just thatโ€”a minority view. Justice Powell, who provided the fifth vote and controlling opinion in Bakke, firmly rejected the notion that societal discrimination constituted a compelling interest. Such an interest presents โ€œan amorphous concept of injury that may be ageless in its reach into the past,โ€ he explained. Id., at 307. It cannot โ€œjustify a [racial] classification that imposes disadvantages upon persons . . . who bear no responsibility for whatever harm the beneficiaries of the [race-based] admissions program are thought to have suffered.โ€ Id., at 310.

The Court soon adopted Justice Powellโ€™s analysis as its own. In the years after Bakke, the Court repeatedly held that ameliorating societal discrimination does not constitute a compelling interest that justifies race-based state action. โ€œ[A]n effort to alleviate the effects of societal discrimination is not a compelling interest,โ€ we said plainly in Hunt, a 1996 case about the Voting Rights Act. 517 U. S., at 909โ€“910. We reached the same conclusion in Croson, a case that concerned a preferential government contracting program. Permitting โ€œpast societal discriminationโ€ to โ€œserve as the basis for rigid racial preferences would be to open the door to competing claims for โ€˜remedial relief โ€™ for every disadvantaged group.โ€ 488 U. S., at 505. Opening that door would shutter anotherโ€”โ€œ[t]he dream of a Nation of equal citizens . . . would be lost,โ€ we observed, โ€œin a mosaic of shifting preferences based on inherently unmeasurable claims of past wrongs.โ€ Id., at 505โ€“506. โ€œ[S]uch a result would be contrary to both the letter and spirit of a constitutional provision whose central command is equality.โ€ Id., at 506.

The dissents here do not acknowledge any of this. They fail to cite Hunt. They fail to cite Croson. They fail to mention that the entirety of their analysis of the Equal Protection Clauseโ€”the statistics, the cases, the historyโ€”has been considered and rejected before. There is a reason the principal dissent must invoke Justice Marshallโ€™s partial dissent in Bakke nearly a dozen times while mentioning Justice Powellโ€™s controlling opinion barely once (Justice Jacksonโ€™s opinion ignores Justice Powell altogether). For what one dissent denigrates as โ€œrhetorical flourishes about colorblindness,โ€ post, at 14 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.), are in fact the proud pronouncements of cases like Loving and Yick Wo, like Shelley and Bollingโ€”they are defining statements of law. We understand the dissents want that law to be different. They are entitled to that desire. But they surely cannot claim the mantle of stare decisis while pursuing it.

The dissents are no more faithful to our precedent on race-based admissions. To hear the principal dissent tell it, Grutter blessed such programs indefinitely, until โ€œracial inequality will end.โ€ Post, at 54 (opinion of Sotomayor, J.). But Grutter did no such thing. It emphasizedโ€”not once or twice, but at least six separate timesโ€”that race-based admissions programs โ€œmust have reasonable durational limitsโ€ and that their โ€œdeviation from the norm of equal treatmentโ€ must be โ€œa temporary matter.โ€ 539 U. S., at 342. The Court also disclaimed โ€œ[e]nshrining a permanent justification for racial preferences.โ€ Ibid. Yet the justification for race-based admissions that the dissent latches on to is just thatโ€”unceasing.

The principal dissentโ€™s reliance on Fisher II is similarly mistaken. There, by a 4-to-3 vote, the Court upheld a โ€œsui generisโ€ race-based admissions program used by the University of Texas, 579 U. S., at 377, whose โ€œgoalโ€ it was to enroll a โ€œcritical massโ€ of certain minority students, Fisher I, 570 U. S., at 297. But neither Harvard nor UNC claims to be using the critical mass conceptโ€”indeed, the universities admit they do not even know what it means. See 1 App. in No. 21โ€“707, at 402 (โ€œ[N]o one has directed anybody to achieve a critical mass, and Iโ€™m not even sure we would know what it is.โ€ (testimony of UNC administrator)); 3 App. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 1137โ€“1138 (similar testimony from Harvard administrator).

Fisher II also recognized the โ€œenduring challengeโ€ that race-based admissions systems place on โ€œthe constitutional promise of equal treatment.โ€ 579 U. S., at 388. The Court thus reaffirmed the โ€œcontinuing obligationโ€ of universities โ€œto satisfy the burden of strict scrutiny.โ€ Id., at 379. To drive the point home, Fisher II limited itself just as Grutter hadโ€”in duration. The Court stressed that its decision did โ€œnot necessarily mean the University may rely on the same policyโ€ going forward. 579 U. S., at 388 (emphasis added); see also Fisher I, 570 U. S., at 313 (recognizing that โ€œGrutter . . . approved the plan at issue upon concluding that it . . . was limited in timeโ€). And the Court openly acknowledged that its decision offered limited โ€œprospective guidance.โ€ Fisher II, 579 U. S., at 379.

The principal dissent wrenches our case law from its context, going to lengths to ignore the parts of that law it does not like. The serious reservations that Bakke, Grutter, and Fisher had about racial preferences go unrecognized. The unambiguous requirements of the Equal Protection Clauseโ€”โ€œthe most rigid,โ€ โ€œsearchingโ€ scrutiny it entailsโ€”go without note. Fisher I, 570 U. S., at 310. And the repeated demands that race-based admissions programs must end go overlookedโ€”contorted, worse still, into a demand that such programs never stop.

Most troubling of all is what the dissent must make these omissions to defend: a judiciary that picks winners and losers based on the color of their skin. While the dissent would certainly not permit university programs that discriminated against black and Latino applicants, it is perfectly willing to let the programs here continue. In its view, this Court is supposed to tell state actors when they have picked the right races to benefit. Separate but equal is โ€œinherently unequal,โ€ said Brown. 347 U. S., at 495 (emphasis added). It depends, says the dissent.

That is a remarkable view of the judicial roleโ€”remarkably wrong. Lost in the false pretense of judicial humility that the dissent espouses is a claim to power so radical, so destructive, that it required a Second Founding to undo. โ€œJustice Harlan knew better,โ€ one of the dissents decrees. Post, at 5 (opinion of Jackson, J.). Indeed he did:

โ€œ[I]n view of the Constitution, in the eye of the law, there is in this country no superior, dominant, ruling class of citizens. There is no caste here. Our Constitution is color-blind, and neither knows nor tolerates classes among citizens.โ€ Plessy, 163 U. S., at 559 (Harlan, J., dissenting).

VI

For the reasons provided above, the Harvard and UNC admissions programs cannot be reconciled with the guarantees of the Equal Protection Clause. Both programs lack sufficiently focused and measurable objectives warranting the use of race, unavoidably employ race in a negative manner, involve racial stereotyping, and lack meaningful end points. We have never permitted admissions programs to work in that way, and we will not do so today.

At the same time, as all parties agree, nothing in this opinion should be construed as prohibiting universities from considering an applicantโ€™s discussion of how race affected his or her life, be it through discrimination, inspiration, or otherwise. See, e.g., 4 App. in No. 21โ€“707, at 1725โ€“1726, 1741; Tr. of Oral Arg. in No. 20โ€“1199, at 10. But, despite the dissentโ€™s assertion to the contrary, universities may not simply establish through application essays or other means the regime we hold unlawful today. (A dissenting opinion is generally not the best source of legal advice on how to comply with the majority opinion.) โ€œ[W]hat cannot be done directly cannot be done indirectly. The Constitution deals with substance, not shadows,โ€ and the prohibition against racial discrimination is โ€œlevelled at the thing, not the name.โ€ Cummings v. Missouri, 4 Wall. 277, 325 (1867). A benefit to a student who overcame racial discrimination, for example, must be tied to that studentโ€™s courage and determination. Or a benefit to a student whose heritage or culture motivated him or her to assume a leadership role or attain a particular goal must be tied to that studentโ€™s unique ability to contribute to the university. In other words, the student must be treated based on his or her experiences as an individualโ€”not on the basis of race.

Many universities have for too long done just the opposite. And in doing so, they have concluded, wrongly, that the touchstone of an individualโ€™s identity is not challenges bested, skills built, or lessons learned but the color of their skin. Our constitutional history does not tolerate that choice.

The judgments of the Court of Appeals for the First Circuit and of the District Court for the Middle District of North Carolina are reversed.

It is so ordered.

Justice Jackson took no part in the consideration or decision of the case in No. 20โ€“1199.

Featured Video

Tags:

CITE THIS ENTRY IN APA FORMAT:

, . (2025, January 11). (2023) Students for Fair Admissions v. Harvard and Students for Fair Admissions v. University of North Carolina. BlackPast.org. https://www.blackpast.org/african-american-history/2023-students-for-fair-admissions-v-harvard-and-students-for-fair-admissions-v-university-of-north-carolina/

Further Reading

Your Title Goes Here

Your content goes here. Edit or remove this text inline or in the module Content settings. You can also style every aspect of this content in the module Design settings and even apply custom CSS to this text in the module Advanced settings.

February 20, 2023 / Contributed by: Otis Alexander

Your Title Goes Here

Your content goes here. Edit or remove this text inline or in the module Content settings. You can also style every aspect of this content in the module Design settings and even apply custom CSS to this text in the module Advanced settings.

February 20, 2023 / Contributed by: Otis Alexander

Your Title Goes Here

Your content goes here. Edit or remove this text inline or in the module Content settings. You can also style every aspect of this content in the module Design settings and even apply custom CSS to this text in the module Advanced settings.

February 20, 2023 / Contributed by: Otis Alexander

Your Title Goes Here

Your content goes here. Edit or remove this text inline or in the module Content settings. You can also style every aspect of this content in the module Design settings and even apply custom CSS to this text in the module Advanced settings.

February 20, 2023 / Contributed by: Otis Alexander

Your Title Goes Here

Your content goes here. Edit or remove this text inline or in the module Content settings. You can also style every aspect of this content in the module Design settings and even apply custom CSS to this text in the module Advanced settings.

February 20, 2023 / Contributed by: Otis Alexander

Your Title Goes Here

Your content goes here. Edit or remove this text inline or in the module Content settings. You can also style every aspect of this content in the module Design settings and even apply custom CSS to this text in the module Advanced settings.

February 20, 2023 / Contributed by: Otis Alexander